Results for 'Lorne S. Cummings'

956 found
Order:
  1.  59
    The financial performance of ethical investment trusts: An australian perspective. [REVIEW]Lorne S. Cummings - 2000 - Journal of Business Ethics 25 (1):79 - 92.
    This study examines whether differences in financial performance exist for investment trusts which base their portfolio selection primarily on an ethical screen, compared to indexes which incorporate a broader spectrum of investments. Results indicate that on a risk-adjusted basis there is an insignificant difference in the financial performance of these trusts against three common market benchmarks. However as to the extent of the directional effect, there does exist slightly superior financial performance by ethical trusts against their respective industry average indexes, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  2. Frontal subcortical circuits: anatomy and function.M. S. Mega & J. L. Cummings - 2001 - In Stephen Salloway, Paul Malloy & James D. Duffy (eds.), The Frontal Lobes and Neuropsychiatric Illness. American Psychiatric Press. pp. 15--32.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  20
    Sunrise ranch as a utopian community.Michael S. Cummings - 1991 - Utopian Studies 3:59-65.
  4.  8
    (1 other version)Modern American Communes: A Dictionary.Michael S. Cummings - 2006 - Utopian Studies 17 (2):398-401.
  5.  26
    The effect of local anesthesia on tactile and vibratory thresholds.S. B. Cummings Jr - 1938 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 23 (4):321.
  6.  25
    Lewis S. Ford, Transforming Process Theism, Foreword by Robert Cummings Neville. [REVIEW]Lewis S. Ford & Robert Cummings Neville - 2003 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 54 (1):61-63.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  20
    Effects of amount of reward on acquisition of a black-white discrimination.Richard S. Weisinger, Lorne F. Parker & Robert C. Bolles - 1973 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 2 (1):27-28.
  8.  61
    Metaphysical Journal.The Mystery of Being. II. Faith & Reality.Man Against Mass Society.Robert D. Cumming, Gabriel Marcel, Bernard Wall, Rene Hague, Donald Mackinnon & G. S. Fraser - 1953 - Journal of Philosophy 50 (23):698.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  19
    Everyday Utopias: The Conceptual Life of Promising Spaces by Davina Cooper.Michael S. Cummings - 2016 - Utopian Studies 27 (3):649-655.
    Everyday Utopias explores a topic that is vital but is too often overlooked by utopian scholars. It is best read in tandem with its 2013 predecessor, Weak Messianism: Essays in Everyday Utopianism, by Michael Gardiner. In a nutshell, Cooper, like Gardiner, argues that although utopian visions may be born in the brains of utopian thinkers, progress toward utopia is what counts, and it must be rooted in present patterns and possibilities. Lest my qualms with the book’s execution overwhelm its value (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Utopian Studies II.Michael S. Cummings & Nicholas D. Smith - 1990 - Utopian Studies 1 (1):130-136.
  11. Hume's Reply to the Achilles Argument.Lorne Falkenstein - 2008 - In Thomas M. Lennon & Robert J. Stainton (eds.), The Achilles of Rationalist Psychology. Springer. pp. 193-214.
    Book 1, Part 4, Section 5 of Hume’s Treatise is taken up with a response to an argument for the immateriality of the soul that Hume considered “remarkable,” and that Kant was later to describes as the “Achilles” (the strongest) of all the arguments for this conclusion. This paper surveys versions of the argument offered by Cudworth, Bayle, and Clarke before going on to argue that Hume’s own treatment of the argument departs from the standard in a number of important (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Hume's answer to Kant.Lorne Falkenstein - 1998 - Noûs 32 (3):331-360.
    Reid's Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense devotes more space to double vision than to any other topic. In what follows, I examine why this subject was so important to Reid and why he dealt with it as he did. I also consider whether his argument for his position begs the question against his main opponents, Berkeley and Robert Smith. I show that, as Reid presented it, it does, but that he could have said more (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  34
    Kant’s First Argument in the Metaphysical Expositions.Lorne Falkenstein - 1989 - Proceedings of the Sixth International Kant Congress 2 (1):219-227.
    This paper argues that Kant's first argument in the metaphysical expositions defends a foundational insight on which much of the rest of his thought depends: that our experience of the spatial properties and relations of things is not based on comparison of the things (matters) found in space or on any form of reasoning (causal or demonstrative). Spatial and temporal relations are originally given in sensory intuition, not constructed or inferred.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Justice.Homer S. Cummings - 1938 - Washington,: U. S. Govt. print. off..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  82
    Consciousness, Time, and Scepticism in Hume's Thought.Lorne Falkenstein - 2024 - New York: Routledge.
    David Hume’s philosophical work presents the reader with a perplexing mix of constructive accounts of empirically guided belief and destructive sceptical arguments against all belief. This book reconciles this conflict by showing that Hume intended his scepticism to be remedial. It immunizes us against the influence of “unphilosophical” causes of belief, determining us to proportion our beliefs to the evidence. In making this case, this book develops Humean positions on topics Hume did not discuss in detail but that are of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Kant’s Account of Sensation.Lorne Falkenstein - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (1):63-88.
    Kant defined ‘sensation’as ‘the effect of an object on the representative capacity, so far as we are affected by it.’ This is, to put it mildly, not one among his more elegant, clear or helpful sayings. And it is merely an instance of a more general malaise. Kant did not say as much about sensation as he should have, and his account-or lack of it-can be seen at the root of many of the difficulties that have plagued his readers.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  60
    Reid's response to Hume's perceptual relativity argument.Lorne Falkenstein - 2011 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):25-49.
    Reid declared Hume's appeal to variation in the magnitude of a table with distance to be the best argument that had ever been offered for the ‘ideal hypothesis’ that we experience nothing but our own mental states. Reid's principal objection to this argument fails to apply to minimally visible points. He did establish that we have reason to take our perceptions to be caused by external objects. But his case that we directly perceive external objects is undermined by what Hume (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  13
    Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - University of Toronto Press.
    This book presents a paragraph-by-paragraph analysis of all of the major arguments and explanations in the "aesthetic" of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. The first part of the book aims to provide a clear analysis of the meanings of the terms Kant uses to name faculties and types of representation, the second offers a thorough account of the reasoning behind the "metaphysical" and "transcendental" expositions, and the third investigates the basis for Kant's major conclusions about space, time, appearances, things in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  19. Naturalism, Normativity, and Scepticism in Hume's Account of Belief.Lorne Falkenstein - 1997 - Hume Studies 23 (1):29-72.
    Hume's scepticism about the ability of demonstrative reasoning to justify many of our most common and important beliefs, such those concerning the connection between causes and effects, does not sit well with his tendency to make normative claims about which beliefs we ought to accept. I argue that Hume's naturalist account of the causes of belief is nonetheless rich enough to provide for normative assessments of belief and even for the modification of beliefs in light of these assessments. I argue, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  64
    Kant's Empiricism.Lorne Falkenstein - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 50 (3):547 - 589.
    It might seem inappropriate to describe Kant as an empiricist. He believed, contrary to the basic empiricist principle, that there are nontrivial propositions that can be known independently of experience. He devoted virtually all of his efforts as a researcher to discovering how it is possible for us to have this "synthetic a priori" knowledge. However, Kant also believed that there are some things that we can know only through sensory experience. Though he did not give these empirical propositions the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  50
    Reid’s Account of the “Geometry of Visibles”: Some Lessons from Helmholtz.Lorne Falkenstein - 2016 - Topoi 35 (2):485-510.
    Drawing on work done by Helmholtz, I argue that Reid was in no position to infer that objects appear as if projected on the inner surface of a sphere, or that they have the geometric properties of such projections even though they do not look concave towards the eye. A careful consideration of the phenomena of visual experience, as further illuminated by the practice of visual artists, should have led him to conclude that the sides of visible appearances either look (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  71
    Berkeley's Argument for Other Minds.Lorne Falkenstein - 1990 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (4):431 - 440.
    The literature on Berkeley is almost unanimous in taking this claim to know the existence of other finite spirits to rest on an argument from analogy. I show that this is not so and that Berkeley uses a causal argument to prove that there are other minds. Questions of the degree to which it is legitimate for Berkeley to appeal to causes, particularly occasional causes, are addressed in the process.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  24
    Fatigue of the vibratory sense.C. H. Wedell & S. B. Cummings - 1938 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 22 (5):429.
  24. Hume and the Contemporary 'Common Sense' Critique of Hume.Lorne Falkenstein - 2016 - In Paul Russell (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of David Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 729-51.
    This paper reviews the principal objections that Hume's Scots "common sense" contemporaries had to his account of the understanding. In the absence of any but the most scant evidence of Hume's own reactions to these criticisms, it weighs what he might have said in his own defense.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  42
    Interpreting Putnam's dialectical method in philosophy.Louise Cummings - 2005 - Metaphilosophy 36 (4):476-489.
    Hilary Putnam's philosophical views have undergone extensive interpretation over many years. One such interpretive work is George Myerson's book Rhetoric, Reason and Society. Myerson's interest in dialogic rationalism leads him to examine the views of many theorists of rationality, philosophers and non-philosophers alike. As a prominent philosopher of rationality, Putnam is at the very center of this examination. Notwithstanding this fact, I contend that Myerson misinterprets the dialectical character of Putnam's philosophy in general and of Putnam's views on rationality in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  37
    David Hume: Essays and Treatises on Philosophical Subjects.Lorne Falkenstein & Neil McArthur - 2013 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    This is the first edition in over a century to present David Hume's Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Dissertation on the Passions, Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, and Natural History of Religion in the format he intended: collected together in a single volume. Hume has suffered a fate unusual among great philosophers. His principal philosophical work is no longer published in the form in which he intended it to be read. It has been divided into separate parts, only some of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  13
    Protection Motivation and Communication through Nanofood Labels: Improving Predictive Capabilities of Attitudes and Purchase Intentions toward Nanofoods.Shirley S. Ho, Agnes S. F. Chuah & Christopher L. Cummings - 2018 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 43 (5):888-916.
    The development and use of nanotechnology in the food industry have grown steadily. While visions for nanofood suggest that the applications will improve quality and safety, they are also controversial for several reasons including potential health risks coupled with difficulty in assessing low-dosage nanoparticle risks as well as values-based objections. In recent years, debate over nanofoods has sparked inquiry into factors that predict public attitudes and purchase intentions. Such studies have investigated the roles of demographics and sociographics, value predispositions toward (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  17
    A Philosophy of Sacred Nature: Prospects for Ecstatic Naturalism.Robert S. Corrington, Sigridur Gudmarsdottir, Joseph M. Kramp, Wade A. Mitchell, Robert Cummings Neville, Jea Sophia Oh, Iljoon Park, Austin J. Roberts, Wesley J. Wildman, Guy Woodward & Martin O. Yalcin (eds.) - 2014 - Lanham: Lexington Books.
    This book introduces Robert Corrington’s “ecstatic naturalism,” a new perspective in understanding “sacred” nature and naturalism, and explores what can be done with this philosophical thought. This is an excellent resource for scholars of Continental philosophy, philosophy of religion, and American pragmatism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  72
    The Role of Material Impressions in Reid's Theory of Vision: A Critique of Gideon Yaffe's “Reid on the Perception of the Visible Figure”.Lorne Falkenstein & Giovanni B. Grandi - 2003 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 1 (2):117-133.
    Reid maintained that the perceptions that we obtain from the senses of smell, taste, hearing, and touch are ‘suggested’ by corresponding sensations. However, he made an exception for the sense of vision. According to Reid, our perceptions of the real figure, position, and magnitude of bodies are suggested by their visible appearances, which are not sensations but objects of perception in their own right. These visible appearances have figure, position, and magnitude, as well as ‘colour,’ and the standard view among (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  2
    Subject Index.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - In Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 457-465.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. (1 other version)Kant’s Argument for the Non-Spatiotemporality of Things in Themselves.Lorne Falkenstein - 1989 - Kant Studien 80 (1-4):265-83.
    Kant's problematic conclusion, that we can know that things in themselves are not in space or time, is shown to follow directly from his claim that space and time are manners of disposition or forms of arrangement in which various items are presented to us in intuition. This argument is not strong enough to rule out certain well-defined senses in which things in themselves "could" possibly be spatio-temporal, but it does show that any sense in which things in themselves could (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32.  41
    Why we need to avoid theorizing about rationality: A Putnamian criticism of Habermas's epistemology.Louise Cummings - 2001 - Social Epistemology 16 (2):117 – 131.
    It is contended that Jurgen Habermas's (1972, 1984) attempts to overcome the problems that positivist thought has caused for theorizing rationality has actually exacerbated positivism's negative effects on conceptualizing rational thought. An overview of Hilary Putnam's (1981) examination of logical positivism's understanding of rationality is presented, emphasizing that positivist approaches toward theorizing rationality are essentially self-refuting in nature since they utilize a metaphysical perspective. Potential objections to the delineation of logical positivism's account of rationality as self-refuting are addressed. Habermas' analysis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Reid’s Account of Localization.Lorne Falkenstein - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (2):305-328.
    This paper contrasts three different positions taken by 18th century British scholars on how sensations, particularly sensations of colour and touch, come to be localized in space: Berkeley’s view that we learn to localize ideas of colour by associating certain purely qualitative features of those ideas with ideas of touch and motion, Hume’s view that visual and tangible impressions are originally disposed in space, and Reid’s view that we are innately disposed to refer appearances of colour to the end of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  24
    Roman Population, Territory, Tribe, City, and Army Size from the Republic's Founding to the Veientane War, 509 BC-400 BC.Lorne H. Ward - 1990 - American Journal of Philology 111 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  25
    Evolutionary Views of Tuberculosis: Indoleamine 2,3‐Dioxygenase Catalyzed Nicotinamide Synthesis Reflects Shifts in Macrophage Metabolism. [REVIEW]Melinda S. Suchard, Clement G. Adu-Gyamfi, Bridgette M. Cumming & Dana M. Savulescu - 2020 - Bioessays 42 (5):1900220.
    Indoleamine 2,3‐dioxygenase (IDO) is the rate‐limiting enzyme in conversion of tryptophan to kynurenines, feeding de novo nicotinamide synthesis. IDO orchestrates materno‐foetal tolerance, increasing human reproductive fitness. IDO mediates immune suppression through depletion of tryptophan required by T lymphocytes and other mechanisms. IDO is expressed by alternatively activated macrophages, suspected to play a key role in tuberculosis (TB) pathogenesis. Unlike its human host, Mycobacterium tuberculosis can synthesize tryptophan, suggesting possible benefit to the host from infection with the microbe. Intriguingly, nicotinamide analogues (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  45
    Space and the Self in Hume's Treatise. [REVIEW]Lorne Falkenstein - 1999 - Hume Studies 25 (1-2):241-249.
    Marina Frasca-Spada's Space and the Self in Hume's Treatise proposes a subjective idealist interpretation of Hume's account of space in part ii of Book I of the Treatise. The book is divided into four chapters. The first deals with Hume's position on infinite divisibility in I ii 1-2, the second with his position on the origin of the idea of space in I ii 3, the third with his account of geometrical knowledge in I ii 4, and the final chapter (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Musical References in Brucioli’s Dialogi and Their Classical and Medieval Antecedents.Anthony M. Cummings - 2010 - Journal of the History of Ideas 71 (2):169-190.
    Among the distinguished intellectuals of sixteenth-century Italy was Antonio Brucioli, renowned for participating in the gatherings in the garden of the Rucellai in Florence during the second decade of the sixteenth century. Since Delio Cantimori’s fundamental article and Giorgio Spini’s fundamental monograph, Brucioli’s Dialogi have been valued for the insight they afford into the discussions of the Rucellai group. Twice in the Dialogi Brucioli offers a revealing discussion of music. The references reflect intellectual traditions of great significance and longevity and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  23
    Kant's Transcendental Aesthetic.Lorne Falkenstein - 2006 - In Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 140–153.
  39. Kant’s Account of Intuition.Lorne Falkenstein - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (2):165-193.
    This paper outlines the history of the distinction between a higher and a lower cognitive function up to Kant. It is argued that Kant initially drew the distinction in Scholastic terms--as a distinction between a capacity to image particulars and a capacity to represent universals. However, features of his project in the Critique led him to reformulate the distinction in terms of immediacy and mediacy. Nonetheless, for certain purposes the older, Scholastic distinction retained its attractiveness, and this is the ground (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  10
    Citation Index.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - In Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 445-452.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  5
    Person Index.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - In Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 453-456.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  3
    3. Sensation and the Matter of Intuition.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - In Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 103-134.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  7
    Summary and Conclusions to Part II.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - In Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 275-284.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  2
    6. The Second Exposition.Lorne Falkenstein - 1995 - In Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic. University of Toronto Press. pp. 186-216.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. (1 other version)Reid's Critique of Berkeley's Position on the Inverted Image.Lorne Falkenstein - 2000 - Reid Studies 4 (1):35-51.
    (This article was republished in lightly re-edited form in _Journal of Scottish Philosophy_ 16 (2018) 175-91.) Reid and Berkeley disagreed over whether we directly perceive objects located outside of us in a surrounding space, commonly revealed by both vision and touch. Berkeley considered a successful account of erect vision to be crucial for deciding this dispute, at one point calling it ‘the principal point in the whole optic theory.’ Reid's critique of Berkeley's position on this topic is very brief, and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  24
    Hume's Project in 'The Natural History of Religion'.Lorne Falkenstein - 2003 - Religious Studies 39 (1):1-21.
    There are good reasons to think that at least a part of Hume's project in the ‘The natural history of religion’ was to buttress a philosophical critique of the reasonableness of religious belief undertaken in other works, and to attack a fundamentalist account of the history of religion and the foundations of morality. But there are also problems with supposing that Hume intended to achieve either of these goals. I argue that two problems in particular – accounting for Hume's neglect (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  75
    Hume on the Idea of a Vacuum.Lorne Falkenstein - 2014 - Hume Studies 39 (2):131-168.
    Hume had two principal arguments for denying that we can have an idea of a vacuum, an argument from the non-entity of unqualified points and an argument from the impossibility of forming abstract ideas of manners of disposition. He also made two serious concessions to the opposed view that we can indeed form ideas of vacua, namely, that bodies that have nothing sensible disposed between them may permit the interposition of other bodies without any apparent motion or occlusion and that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48. Condillac's paradox.Lorne Falkenstein - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (4):403-435.
    : I argue that Condillac was committed to four mutually inconsistent propositions: that the mind is unextended, that sensations are modifications of the mind, that colours are sensations, and that colours are extended. I argue that this inconsistency was not just the blunder of a second-rate philosopher, but the consequence of a deep-seated tension in the views of early modern philosophers on the nature of the mind, sensation, and secondary qualities and that more widely studied figures, notably Condillac's contemporaries, Hume (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49. Intuition and construction in Berkeley's account of visual space.Lorne Falkenstein - 1994 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 32 (1):63-84.
    This paper examines Berkeley's attitude toward our perception of spatial relations on the two- dimensional visual field. This is a topic on which there has been some controversy. Historians of visual theory have tended to suppose that Berkeley took "all" spatial relations to be derived in the way our knowledge of depth is: from association of more primitive sensations which are themselves in no way spatial. But many philosophers commenting on Berkeley have supposed that he takes our awareness of two- (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  11
    Phenomenology and Deconstruction, Volume Two: Method and Imagination.Robert Denoon Cumming - 1991 - University of Chicago Press.
    "Husserl had captured me, I saw everything in terms of the perspectives of his philosophy," wrote Sartre of his conversion to Husserl's phenomenology. In the present volume Cumming analyzes Sartre's transformation of Husserl's phenomenological method into a rudimentary dialectic. Cumming thus provides an introduction to phenomenology itself, and more generally to the ways in which debts to previous philosophies can be refurbished in later philosophies. He shows how phenomenology, which for Husserl was a theory of knowledge in which "we can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 956